Institute for Christian Teaching
Education Department, General Conference of
Seventh-day Adventists
A BIBLICAL PERSPECTIVE ON THE
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
Leonard R. Brand
2nd Symposium on the Bible and Adventist
Scholarship
Juan Dolio, Dominican Republic
March 15-20, 2004
A BIBLICAL PERSPECTIVE ON THE
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
Leonard R. Brand, Ph.D.
Professor of Biology and Paleontology
Loma Linda University
Modern
science began in Christian Europe, and many great scientists in past centuries
viewed their scientific work as thinking God’s thoughts after Him. This attitude toward science and religion
went into a serious decline, until it seemed that science had eliminated the
possibility of theology as a source of knowledge. However, more recent thinking by philosophers
of science has set the stage for suggesting a different view. We will be dealing in this paper with
biblical Christianity, and will not discuss other religions.
Christianity and the origins of
modern science
At
times in history scientific study was much more alive in other places than it
was in the Western world, so why did modern science arise in Western Europe
instead of in China or some other place?
There is reason to believe that Christianity provided the ideal culture
for the origin of modern science (Polkinghorne 1994, Ratzsch 2000). The creation of the universe by a rational,
intelligent God explains why the universe is so intelligible and open to our
scientific investigation. Since
Christianity offered such a rational God, this can explain why Christians
expected the world to be understandable, and why it is worthwhile investing
one’s energy and time into systematic investigation of nature. Science must also assume that nature is uniform,
with universal processes and patterns.
For a Christian, these characteristics and assumptions of science are
founded in belief that the universe was created by a rational God who is
faithful and consistent. A secular
scientist does not have such a foundation, and must generally accept these
concepts as mere assumptions.
Science
as an institution has now rejected the creation account as its foundation, but
continues to be successful. Will denial
of the existence of a rational Creator eventually weaken science by
undercutting its foundation? Or now that
science is in motion does it have sufficient momentum to maintain its rapid
progress? Time will tell.
The philosophy of science - changing
views on how knowledge is acquired and evaluated
As
modern science developed in the 17th to early 20th
centuries, scientists and philosophers encouraged a more objective and rational
study of nature, by empirical observation, than had been practiced before. I will refer to Francis Bacon’s understanding
of science as an example of the traditional, positivist understanding of
science developed early in that process.
He thought that prejudices or theories are bad and should be avoided. Our task, according to Bacon, is to rid our
minds of prior prejudices and theories, and then objectively collect data and
let the data lead us to a true understanding of nature (Popper 1963, Ratzsch
2000). Bacon’s concept of science is now
understood to be unrealistic, and the most naive part of Bacon’s philosophy was
his belief that we can begin the scientific process by purging our minds of all
bias or prejudices (Popper 1963). How
would we know what ideas to purge? In
actuality a mind purged of all “biases” would be an empty mind, not an
objective mind.
In the positivist philosophy of science two
important issues were demarcation (determining the boundary between science and
nonscience) and confirmation of theories (how to determine if a theory had been
demonstrated to be correct, or verified).
In the early 20th century logical positivism was the most
influential school of thought. According
to logical positivism the confirmation of a theory can occur only by empirical
data that verify, or indicate the truth of the theory. A theory is valid science, satisfying the
demands of demarcation, if it can be verified by empirical observation. Everything that could not be so verified was
nonsense. Thus science was considered
the only route to understanding; all other knowledge was not knowledge at
all. This materialistic outlook
considered the material and physical to be real, but there could not be any
human religious or ethical knowledge unless such knowledge was independently
verified by science (Murphy 1990; Ratzsch 2000).
Positivism
declined as it became evident that it could not effectively deal with some
areas of reality, and that the verification criterion did not work. Karl Popper led the way in emphasizing that
just because a series of observations support a statement does not finally
establish it to be true. We never know
when new observations may demonstrate the statement, or at least part of the
statement, to be false (Popper 1959, 1963; Ratzsch 2000). We may hypothesize that all crows are black,
and support the statement by observation of 1,000 black crows, but then finding
one white crow can prove the statement to be false. Of course most scientific theories are more
complex than the color of crows, but no matter how simple or complex they are
we can never verify a theory or demonstrate it to be true, because there is
always the possibility that it may in the future be falsified by new data.
In
Popper’s philosophy of science, research begins with some observation or
problem to be solved. Then the scientist
thinks of a theory to explain the observation, and indicates what type of data
would disprove, or falsify the theory.
As long as research does not falsify the theory, it remains viable. Thus we cannot truly verify theories, but we
can identify false theories and by this process gradually improve our
understanding of natural phenomena (Popper 1959, 1963). Popper’s philosophy answers the big questions
of demarcation and verification in the following way. Any theory or hypothesis is scientific (meets
the demarcation criterion) if it can, at least in principle, be tested, that is
if it can be contradicted by empirical data.
The confirmation criterion cannot be met by proving or verifying a
theory, but simply by holding a theory only as long as it hasn’t been
falsified.
Popper’s
falsification concept was an improvement over positivism, but falsification
also has its limits. New data may appear
to refute a theory, but further research may reveal that we misunderstood that
new data, and the theory was not falsified after all. This is a very real problem, since it is not
possible to falsify a theory with confidence.
However, in principle the concept of testing a theory by observations or
experiments that have the potential to falsify it is still an effective
technique, as long as we remember that falsification is not final. As our
knowledge grows we may discover that the theory was actually not
falsified. Science is always a
continuing search, that doesn’t reach absolute truth.
Popper’s
philosophy of science abandoned the rigidly rational criteria of the
traditional view, and recognized the human element in science. He saw that there is always a need for human
choice or judgment in research (Ratzsch 2000).
Science was no longer seen as resting on a solid foundation, but was
compared by Popper (1959, p. 54-55) to a building erected not on solid bedrock,
but on piles driven into a swamp. They
are not driven down to any natural base, but are driven in until “we are
satisfied that the piles are firm enough to carry the structure, at least for the
time being.” In this new view of science
it was no longer reasonable to claim that topics outside of science were
nonsense.
The
human element in science became even more evident in the philosophy of Thomas
Kuhn (1962, 1970), that “has placed humans and human subjectivity (in the form
of values of the community of scientists) in the center of science” (Ratzsch
2000, p. 50). Based on his study of the
history of scientific theories, Kuhn concluded that scientists do not generally
try to disprove their theories. Rather
each scientist typically works within a scientific paradigm (a broad,
explanatory theory; e.g the theory of evolution). They do not try to test the paradigm, but
assume it is true and use it to guide their exploration of new phenomena within
the paradigm’s domain. This process Kuhn
called normal science, because that is what scientists normally do.
As
normal science progresses, anomalies may be discovered - phenomena that do not
seem to fit the expectations of the paradigm.
If these anomalies persistently defy efforts to resolve them, this can
lead to what Kuhn called a crisis state for the paradigm. Science never abandons a theory or paradigm
without another one to replace it, but a crisis may stimulate a few creative
scientists to develop an alternate paradigm.
At that point it is not clear which paradigm is correct, and the choice
between the old paradigm (which has only failed with a few problems) and the
new one (which has not yet established a track record) is often made for less
than objective reasons. Such choices can
even be described as a “conversion” process that leads a scientist to see
things in an entirely new and different way from how he/she saw them before
(Kuhn 1962, 1970). If the new paradigm
replaces the old, a scientific revolution has occurred, and normal science now
proceeds under the new paradigm. The
revolution process cannot be defined by rigorous logical criteria, but as the
result of a changing consensus of opinion among scientists working in that
field.
Further
philosophical work has resulted in criticisms that parts of Kuhn’s philosophy
are not adequately supported by historical data (e.g. Laudan 1977), but it is
still recognized that science is influenced by subjective human elements. Kuhn has responded to his critics (Kuhn
2000), and there were other important philosophers of science in the 20th
century (e.g. Reichenbach 1951, and Feyerabend 1978, 1987). Feyerabend (1978) went so far as to urge that
we should not try to define a scientific method, because rational boundaries
defined by a scientific method will inhibit progress toward finding some
legitimate new knowledge. We will
briefly consider the works of Laudan (1977) and Lakatos (1978), who have
provided sophisticated contemporary philosophies of science. Moreland (1989) and Ratzsch (2000) have
written helpful analyses of the philosophy of science from a Christian
perspective.
Lakatos
believed the history of science is best described as competition through time
between competing research programs. A
research program consists of a core theory, and a set of auxiliary
hypotheses. The core theory is central
to the research program, and is protected from falsification by the “protective
belt” of auxiliary hypotheses, in order to give the core sufficient opportunity
to be fully developed. When potentially
falsifying data appear, it is the auxiliary hypotheses that are modified or
replaced. The theory that all life has arisen
by evolution is an example of a core theory, with its protective belt of
changeable auxiliary hypotheses of specific evolutionary mechanisms.
A
research program is considered progressive or degenerating according to several
criteria, the most important of which is whether it is successful in predicting
novel, hitherto unexpected findings, at least some of which can be successfully
corroborated. Thus the choice between
competing research programs is not based on our ability to determine which one
is more true, but on the programs’ relative ability to increase scientific knowledge. Both demarcation and confirmation are based
on this relative success at increasing scientific knowledge. Science is still perceived as a rational
activity, but it is now recognized that science is affected by sociology,
economics, and other very human factors (Murphy 1990; Lakatos 1978).
The
history of science shows that a theory may be successful in stimulating
scientific progress, and consequently be widely accepted by the scientific
community, and yet later be rejected because the accumulating evidence no
longer supports it. Consequently, if at
a given time there is a strong consensus among scientists regarding the truth
of a particular theory, this consensus may result from philosophical or
sociological factors, rather than from a body of evidence demonstrating the
truth of the theory (Kuhn 1970; Lakatos 1978).
For example, could the scientific consensus that all life forms resulted
from evolution, result from a common anti-supernatural philosophical
commitment, rather than from the adequacy of the evidence?
Laudan’s
(1977) philosophy of science has similarities with that of Lakatos, but he uses
the term research traditions instead of research programs. A research tradition is also evaluated by
comparison with other research traditions, on the basis of its ability to
increase scientific knowledge by predicting novel, previously unexpected,
findings waiting to be discovered by diligent researchers.
The
decisions as to whose philosophical concepts (Bacon, Popper, Kuhn, etc.) are
better have been made primarily from study of the history of scientific ideas,
how the participants in science evaluated those ideas, and how they made their
choices between theories.
Implications for theology
Since
the Enlightenment, authority has no longer been accepted as a legitimate
determiner of what is reliable knowledge.
It could be argued that this has destroyed the rational credibility of
Christian theism, since it depends on the authority of Scripture. This would appear to be true, unless we see
reasons to believe that Scripture is worthy of more trust than human
authorities.
The
traditional, positivist, philosophy of science left no room for theology to
influence science. The scholarly world
still is generally skeptical of theism, but the views of philosophers of
science in the 20th century have undercut rational objections to
considering theology as a legitimate area of knowledge. Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and Laudan have
revealed that science is influenced by many subjective human influences. They have also shown that the old demarcation
and confirmation criteria don’t work.
There is overlap of science and other fields, and it is not possible to
draw a sharp line between science and these other fields of inquiry (Moreland
1989; Ratzsch 2000). Theology and
science are still, in important ways, quite different, but I believe there are
reasons to propose that theology and faith can play a legitimate role in
influencing science.
In
fact Laudan claims that it may be “irrational and prejudicial” to exclude
philosophical, religious and moral issues from scientific decision making
(Laudan 1997, p. 132). The problem of
evil, in the form of pain and suffering, according to Laudan, “is at its core
an empirical problem par excellence: how can one maintain one’s belief
in a benevolent, omnipotent deity in the face of all of the death, disease, and
natural disasters which are a daily element of our experience” (Laudan 1977, p.
190)? As we will see, the solution of
this problem is crucial if theism is to be defensible to many people in this
scientific age.
Laudan
also argues that Judeo-Christian theology makes many historical claims about
the existence of persons and the occurrence of events that should be testable
by empirical methods (Laudan 1977). If
it could be shown that ideas arising from theism, e.g., can be progressive in
advancing scientific knowledge, then contemporary understanding of science
would have difficulty denying the validity of such ideas. Of course this interaction between science
and religion must be carefully defined or it could be a source of problems, and
we will now focus on this topic.
What should be the relationship
between science and religion?
There are various ways to define the
types of possible relations between science and religion (Barbour 1990;
Peacocke 1993; Ratzsch 2000), but I am going to compare a set of three models
for this relationship, based on how much allowance we make for religion to
influence scientific thinking. These
models will be:
1. Isolation. No relationship is allowed between science and
religion; they remain isolated from each other.
The philosophy of naturalism dictates that science reject any
explanations involving the supernatural.
Religion is at most an emotional experience and is not relevant to
scientific issues.
2. Parallel but separate. This model seeks to understand the
relationship between science and religion, because they are both accepted as
sources of truth. However, religion is
not allowed to influence science. The
search for truth is not an integrated cooperation between religion and science,
but religion and science remain separate, searching in parallel to each
other. Science, in practice, follows
methodological naturalism, which means that science, purely as a practical
method, never considers any divine action as a possible explanation of any
phenomena (although it does not deny the possible existence of god).
3. Interaction. This model encourages active interaction
between science and religion in topics where they make overlapping claims,
because both are accepted as sources of cognitive knowledge about the
universe. Allow feedback between them,
to encourage deeper thinking in both areas and provide an antidote to carelessness
on both sides. Both religion and science
can make factual suggestions to the other, which can be the basis for careful
thought and hypothesis testing. This
model respects the scientific process, but also recognizes truth in Scripture. It aims to be an open-ended search for truth,
not bound by the rules of naturalism.
Although it may appear that the Christian using this model is bound by
theistic rules, in actuality we do not need to fear that open-minded scientific
study of God’s nature, in the long run, will contradict God’s message in
Scripture - the Christian can afford to be fair with the evidence.
There
aren’t clear lines between these three models; there can no doubt be some
options between these three, but the data in nature and in Scripture limit the
number of viable options. A number of
prominent writers can be confidently placed in one or the other of these
models, and they will illustrate the differences between the models.
Model 1: Isolation
This
first model isolates scientific explanations from any religious influence, and
is characteristic of many authors who have written on the subject of creation
and evolution. This entirely secular
approach appears to be the closest to what could be thought of as an “official”
description of science as practiced in the 20th century and the
beginning of the 21st century.
The philosophy of naturalism dominates this model, which does not allow
science to accept any hypothesis that requires or implies any supernatural
influence in the universe at any time in history.
Naturalism
comes in two versions: philosophical naturalism denies the existence of god,
but methodological naturalism does not make any claims against the existence of
a god. It is just a method of science
that does not allow explanations invoking miracles. In either case the practical result is the
same; neither philosophical or methodological naturalism allow consideration of
any hypothesis that implies, e.g., that life has been created by God, or that
there has been any other divine intervention in history. This philosophy has at times been expressed
very candidly: “If there is one rule, one criterion that makes an idea
scientific, it is that it must invoke naturalistic explanations for
phenomena, and those explanations must be testable solely by the criteria of our
five senses” (Eldredge 1982, p. 82, emphasis in original). In a later book (Eldredge 2001) he softened
that statement some, but the concept is still basically the same. Richard Dawkins (1986, 1996, 1998) is an
outspoken advocate of the belief that life is the result of the blind forces of
physics, with no purpose in mind. Some
other anti-creationist authors avoid expressly advocating naturalism, but the
material they present is clearly based on a theory of origins resulting from a
naturalistic scientific framework (Kitcher 1982; Futuyma 1995; Ruse 1996;
National Academy of Sciences 1999).
Following a naturalistic model to its logical conclusions implies that
pain, suffering and death are a natural result of the laws of nature, and there
is no other meaning for them to be found - we need to grow up and live with
this.
So
far I have only discussed this model from the standpoint of science, isolated
from religious influence. The other
side of the relationship is also important; what would religion be like if
isolated from any scientific influence?
I will not discuss this in detail, but it should be pointed out that
scientific study has helped us to revise a number of ideas that were once a
part of religious beliefs, and realize that they are not really supported in
Scripture. For example we now recognize
that species of animals are not fixed and unchangeable, and the sun does not
revolve around the earth.
Critique of Model 1: Isolation
In
evaluating this model, a critical question is whether science is an open-ended
search for truth, wherever the evidence may lead? Or is it a game, defined by a set of rules,
that seeks to find answers as far as it can go within those rules? For many scientists the relevant rules in the
study of origins are defined by naturalism, and even if life was actually
created by God, the rules determine that science can never consider that
hypothesis, no matter what the evidence indicates. Creationists are often accused of being unwilling
to allow their creationist beliefs to be considered as a hypothesis, subject to
possible refutation by the evidence. My
reply is - I will consider my creationist beliefs as a hypothesis to be tested,
to the same extent that you will allow your naturalistic beliefs to be a
hypothesis to be tested. I will argue
that science as a rule-bound game that cannot consider some hypotheses is not a
legitimate scholarly exercise. That may
sound naive, but I am well aware that any quick refutation of either view will
not be forthcoming - the universe is too complex to yield easy answers to such
big questions. And in principle, modern
understanding of the philosophy of science does not provide rational support
for the exclusion of some hypotheses from consideration, even if those
hypotheses will be very difficult for science to come to grips with.
The
application of naturalism to the origins of life and of the diversity of
organisms is being challenged by scholars in the Intelligent Design (ID)
movement, led by Phillip Johnson and others (Behe 1996; Moreland 1989, 1994;
Dembski 1998, 1999; Johnson 1991, 1995, 1997, 2000; Ratzsch 2001; Dembski and
Kushiner 2001). Advances in molecular
biology make it increasingly difficult to justify excluding the hypothesis that
life requires an intelligent inventor - that idea must be at least open for
candid discussion. If science is going
to be an open minded search for truth, it cannot arbitrarily exclude some
hypotheses. A book by Pennock (1999)
aimed to refute the scientific status of ID, and claims to have done so. However, for a creationist who accepts at
least microevolution, speciation, and the evolution of languages within several
created language groups, Pennock’s book contains little or nothing in the way
of substantive scientific arguments. It
is primarily one long argument that naturalism is the only valid philosophy,
and science is the only way to find truth.
In written criticisms of ID that I have read, this type of philosophical
rather than substantive scientific response is common.
Model 2: Parallel but separate
The
writings of Peacocke (1993), Polkinghorne (1994, 1998, 2000), Barbour (1974,
1990) and Murphy (1990, 1997, 2002) will illustrate what I mean by the parallel
but separate model. Murphy has
doctorates in philosophy of science and in theology, and the other three
authors are scientists as well as theologians.
These writers don’t agree on everything, but they share the same basic
theology and approach to the relationship between science and religion. They believe in God as the ruler of the
universe and, and in Jesus Christ as God’s supreme revelation to
humankind. They seek to understand God’s
revelation and how it gives us hope and salvation.
They
also accept the entire theory of evolution and of the origin of life from
non-living material as understood by science today. They agree that evolution through hundreds of
millions of years has been God’s method of creation, including the evolution of
humans and apes from common ancestors (theistic evolution). In their belief system there was no literal
Garden of Eden or Adam and Eve. There
was no time when humans lived as innocents in a perfect paradise, and there was
no fall into sin as many Christians believe.
Although they don’t discuss the concept of Satan, their theology does
not seem to have any place for such a being.
Evil, pain and suffering did not result from human sin, but are a
natural part of the evolution process (death, disease, predation, extinction,
etc. are seen in the fossil record for over 500 million years, in conventional
geologic time, before human fossils appear; Fig. 1).
Figure
1. The
sequence in which various groups of fossils appear in the geological column,
with ages as determined by radiometric dating (from Brand 1997).
These
individuals object to allowing religion to influence science. Even though they claim to be supportive of
some version of a Dialogue or Integration model of the relation between science
and religion (Barbour 1990; Peacocke 1993; Polkinghorne 1998), they interpret
this relationship very differently from my integration model. For them, science must proceed without
interference, and religion seeks answers only to questions that science can’t
address. Religion and science are kept
separate, but actually they are only partially separated, by a one-way
door. In their system religion can learn
from science, but science does not learn from religion, and religion does not
“correct” science. The two are parallel
in that both are taken seriously as a search for truth, but they are separate
in that religion does not influence science.
Thus they actually accept methodological naturalism, but are different
from Model 1 in that they do see the search for religious truth to be a valid
scholarly exercise.
But
we can ask how this system can work, since Scripture and science in some cases
speak to the same issues and say opposite things? Three examples are the creation of life, the
creation of humans, and the fall into sin.
Their answer is that it only seems like the Bible and science
disagree, but we must understand that the Bible is only presenting spiritual
insights. It is a serious mistake if we
interpret the events literally. A phrase
they often use to describe this situation is that Scripture is to be “taken seriously
but not literally.”
What
does it mean to take something “seriously but not literally?” In any conversation regarding a topic that is
not just emotional, but has some content, what would I mean if I take a
friend’s statements “seriously but not literally?” In that case I am in fact not taking him
seriously at all, but am discarding his statements as unworthy of being
believed, while giving his ideas some type of metaphorical interpretation,
perhaps to avoid unduly embarrassing the person. If you are discussing with your teenage
children the meaning of sex and the types of relationships in which sex will be
constructive or not constructive, will you be pleased if they take you
seriously but not literally?
There
are some qualifications that are needed in this discussion, or it could be
misunderstood. There are things in
Scripture that even the most conservative among us will probably not read
literally; for example the parable about Abraham and Lazarus (Luke
16:19-31). That parable has features that
do not appear intended to be taken literally.
The same could be argued for a number of other details in
Scripture. In this paper I am concerned
about basic Christian beliefs, not details.
Also,
if a child comes running and tells us that the yard is washing away from a
flood (perhaps a broken water pipe), we may indeed take him seriously but not
literally. Whether it is appropriate to
take an oral or written statement seriously and literally will depend on
our confidence in the level of understanding of the author of the
statement. Whether we accept biblical
statements about such things as a one-week creation event literally will be
greatly influenced by our view of God’s relation to Scripture. Is the creation week the naive understanding
of Moses, or did God more directly instruct Moses, to be sure we are not misled
about how life began? In other words,
what is the nature of inspiration?
In
taking Scripture “seriously but not literally” we are deciding that God has not
committed Himself to reliable and trustworthy communication with us; that He
has not taken the effort to communicate in ways that would convey timeless
propositional truth for all eras of human history in spite of cultural
differences (certainly the God of the universe has the wisdom to know how to do
that if He chose to). The decision to
interpret Scripture in this way has often been made on the basis that
scientific conclusions are the standard for judging biblical statements, and
scientific findings rule out literal interpretations of Scripture. In this situation I maintain that “Seriously
but not literally” is a way to accept scientific conclusions about origins,
rather than challenge those conclusions, while trying to salvage something from
Scripture. But is this approach facing
reality? If science is correct in all
its conclusions about origins, is Scripture worth salvaging, or has the Bible’s
message simply been refuted?
This
may not seem relevant to the philosophy of science, but it is relevant to
epistemology in general - how do we find truth?
In my reading in the sources cited in this section, it seems clear that
the decision to take Scripture “seriously but not literally” even when it
affects core Christian beliefs is based on contemporary scientific
interpretations. If we believe science’s
conclusions that all life forms have resulted from a long evolution process, we
cannot simultaneously believe that these life forms were literally created in
the manner described in Genesis. The
authors cited here believe that in any situation of this type, science trumps
Scripture. But I suggest that the
scientific tentativeness advocated by recent developments in the philosophy of
science should encourage us to periodically reevaluate such a firm commitment
to unquestioning acceptance of contemporary scientific interpretations. Otherwise we are descending into a realm of
scientific dogma that cannot be questioned.
Our
philosophy of science matters to a Christian, because it can strongly impact
theology. The application of the
“parallel but separate” model has led to a theology that attempts to deal with
the empirical problem of pain and suffering, but reaches a very different
conclusion from traditional Christian thinking.
We will consider whether that conclusion is worthy of being taken
seriously (and literally).
In
the references listed above for Peacocke, Polkinghorne, Barbour and Murphy it
is accepted that life arose through the laws of nature, without the assistance
of divine intervention, and life then diverged into many different categories
of plants and animals through the action of “chance and law” - mutation and
natural selection. They recognize that
Darwinian mutations occur by chance, meaning that the mutation process does not
know what the needs of the organism will be.
Mutations just happen, for good or for ill, but then the natural
selection process preserves mutations that are beneficial in that organism’s
environment, and weeds out other mutations.
These
authors accept the scientific belief that this process has produced all of
life, and has led to the evolution of conscious and then self-conscious beings,
and finally to spiritually aware humans.
This conclusion is, of course, contrary to a literal reading of Genesis,
but they warn that any kind of literal reading of Genesis is a seriously
defective view, and that Genesis must be taken “seriously but not
literally.” “Science can get on with its
own task without needing a kind of spurious help from religion” (Polkinghorne
1994, p. 21-22). They advocate that
theology, in this scientific age, must use the same criteria of reasonableness
as science itself uses (e.g. Murphy 1990).
Religion, they say, does not have access to any privileged source such
as revelation. Genesis is only
considered as “theological writing,” and the Genesis story is a metaphor
asserting only that “all that exists does so because of the will of God”
(Polkinghorne 1994, p. 50). The Garden
of Eden is an analogy of the innocence of our hominid ancestors before they
became self-conscious and conscious of God.
The biblical fall into sin was actually the turning toward self, after
humans evolved to the point of being aware of God and of self (Polkinghorne
1998, p. 64), or “Adam’s story is Everyman’s journey from innocence to
responsibility and sin” (Barbour 1990, p. 206).
How
can this theology explain pain and suffering, disease, death, natural disasters
like earthquakes and floods (natural evil), and cruelty, concentration camps,
and murder (moral evil)? All four of
these authors explain it in essentially the same way. They have concluded that if God had imposed
his will on the world, nature and humankind would not have been free. The only way God could give the world the
gift of freedom was to let the world “make itself”, allowing it to develop in
its own way through the operation of chance and law - mutation and natural
selection, and/or through the operation of the uncertainty (quantum mechanics
and the Heisenberg uncertainty principle) that functions at the microscopic and
sub-atomic levels. The uncertainties in
these processes were what allowed freedom to emerge in nature generally, and in
human freedom specifically. But the
chance element in this process not only produced the freedom necessary to
realize the full potential of self-conscious, God-conscious beings. The same process also of necessity produced
the natural evil that is so destructive.
The freedom and the evil came as a package deal, and “even god cannot
have one without the other” (Peacocke 1993, p. 125). A new generation of life only arises through
death of the previous generation, and this is the only way, in their
evolution-derived living world, that higher levels of animal life can
arise. This, they say, is the only way that
humankind could originate, with our freedom and with all the pain and suffering
that inevitably accompanied it, that not even God could prevent. “Most of the suffering in nature (that is not
caused by us) is natural; it simply needs to be present in order for there to
be life at all, especially for there to be life like ourselves” (Murphy 2002,
p. 54). Barbour even says that “Christ
was a focal point of God’s activity and self-revelation . . . a new stage in
evolution . . . part of the continuous process that runs back through Australopithecus
and the early forms of life” (Barbour 1990, p. 211).
This
concept has many theological consequences.
Death and evil were not the result of any human action, since there was
no Adam and Eve and no human Fall. Thus
the classical explanation of the redemptive work of Christ in saving us from
the effects of sin is not correct. Those
stories are considered to be only mythological.
These authors then explain that God does not walk away and leave us to
suffer, but He suffers with us. Jesus
hanging on the cross was God (but, for some authors, in a merely human form)
suffering with us in our pain and suffering.
Critique of Model 2: Parallel but
Separate
I
see a series of problems that make the above scenario unsatisfying. First of all, their conclusion that pain and
suffering are inevitable natural results if God allows us to have freedom
depends entirely on their assumption that life is the result of evolution. But I have not found evidence in the writings
of these four authors to indicate an awareness of the weak points in the
Darwinian theory. They make the mistake
of accepting Darwinism as a package deal, without recognizing that different
parts of the theory could have very different levels of support from the
evidence. The evidence for microevolution
and speciation is very convincing, but these authors also explain all increase
in complexity of life as the result of law and chance - mutation and natural
selection. The underlying genetic
process in this proposed large-scale evolution depends on some important
unsupported assumptions.
The
laws of nature are critical for the existence and uniformity of the universe
and the existence of life. However, life
is also entirely dependant on another critical factor - the information coded
in DNA and proteins. This information is
like a series of written instructions for making biological molecules, and
making them at the right place and right time.
These instructions are like the words and paragraphs in this article -
there is no law in nature that specifies whether D should come after E or H
should come before M. Such order in DNA
or on this page only results from the operation of intelligence - the
information has to be invented.
Evolution
claims that mutation and natural selection can accomplish the same result
without intelligence, but this is strictly a hypothesis, and is the most
serious weakness in evolution theory.
Natural selection can only accomplish anything constructive if mutation
just happens to provide the right mutations when they are needed,
and it is not at all clear that this is a realistic hypothesis (Spetner 1998;
Brand 1997; Behe 1996). The natural
genetic changes (e.g. resistance to insecticides) or laboratory mutations often
cited as evidence for evolution of new features tend to turn out, on closer
inspection, to have other explanations (Spetner 1998) that are not consistent
with the evolution of new biological information.
The
history of science shows a series of apparently well-supported theories that
changed considerably or were rejected because of accumulation of new
evidence. Has that self-correction
process ceased, and are our current biological theories in no danger of being
refuted? Peacocke, Polkinghorne,
Barbour, and Murphy may be building their theology on a scientific basis that
will eventually leave them sitting on shifting sand.
Their
belief that God can only give us freedom through the operation of the
uncertainties of the sub-atomic world of quantum mechanics and/or the operation
of chance in mutation and natural selection, is strictly an assumption. What evidence do they have that there is any
connection between these chance processes and the freedom of choice exhibited
by humans, or any other type of freedom in nature? It seems likely that free will operates
through the features God built into the amazing complexity of our brain
cells. Freedom is the result of a brain
invented by a super genius.
The
world of cancer, earthquakes, accidents, death, child abuse, and Auschwitz is
not “free” at all; it is just dysfunctional.
If evolution, with its inevitable result of pain and suffering was God’s
way of creating, this says that God was not able to use a better system. Such an impotent god did not know how to
design and construct a brain capable of making free choices, and was not able
to make a world that originally functioned harmoniously, as described in
Scripture. I propose that either the
basic concepts in Genesis should be accepted as the true and literal description
of the history of life on earth, or else I have to wonder why Scripture and its
“god” would be interesting to me at all.
If such a god was hanging on the cross in solidarity with our suffering,
is he worthy of my worship, or merely of my pity? The conclusions reached in this parallel
but separate model do not come from Scripture, but are imposed on Scripture
by a particular philosophy of science and religion.
Those
who have proposed this theology have thought through the issues very carefully,
and have described the theology that logically follows if the fossil record
resulted from the evolution of life forms over many millions of years (theistic
evolution; progressive creation also leads to substantially similar theological
conclusions), rather than a literal creation week followed by the Fall into
sin, and later by the geological catastrophe described in Genesis. I cannot fault their principal conclusions, provided
their philosophy is correct. But is
their approach the only intellectually respectable way, or is there a viable alternative? We will consider this next.
Model 3; Interaction
Many
scholars of this generation, including committed Christians, have rejected any
notion of encouraging active interaction between science and religion. I understand their reasons for this, and I
also reject some common types of interaction.
Moreland (1989) and Ratzsch (2000) discuss some of these problems
also. However, I hope to convince you
that there is a better way for such interaction to proceed, that avoids the
pitfalls, real or imagined, that can derail attempts to constructively
integrate faith and science. Below we
will take some time to discuss these pitfalls, because understanding how to
avoid such pitfalls is a key to defining a better integration method. We will then discuss the method by which I
find that ideas from Scripture can in very practical ways contribute to
scientific progress.
We
will first compare the interpretation of Scripture in models 2 and 3. The interpretation of scripture used by
scholars in the parallel but separate model is likely to include several
or all of the following: 1) God may have impressed Bible authors to write, but
He did not communicate to them the ideas or “facts” they wrote; 2) the human
mind, in this age of advanced learning, is quite capable of judging the truth
of biblical statements; 3) many of the “events” described in the Bible were
symbolic or allegorical, not literal, historical events. Examples of the latter could include the
7-day creation, a global flood with an ark full of animals and people, the
Israelites’ miraculous crossings through two bodies of water, Jesus’ miracles,
Jesus’ bodily resurrection, and a literal, personal devil. If this approach to Scripture is correct in
its interpretation of core concepts of Christian theology, it would make little
sense to look to the Bible for insights in earth history, or in many other
scholarly areas of research.
The
interaction model that I will propose takes Scripture more literally than
Peacocke, Polkinghorne, Barbour, and Murphy are willing to do. This more conservative approach to Scripture
can be briefly summarized with Ellen White’s description of it, as “the
language of the Bible should be explained according to its obvious meaning, unless
a symbol or figure is employed” (GC 599).
“It (the Bible) was designed for the common people, and the
interpretation given by the common people, when aided by the Holy Spirit,
accords best with the truth as it is in Jesus (5T 331). “A sense of the power and wisdom of God, and
of our inability to comprehend His greatness, should inspire us with humility,
and we should open His word, as we would enter His presence, with holy
awe. When we come to the Bible, reason
must acknowledge an authority superior to itself, and heart and intellect must
bow before the great I AM” (SC 110).
This approach accepts the events described in the Bible as actual
historical happenings, including the miracles and God’s literal communication
of ideas and facts to at least some Bible writers such as Moses, Daniel, Paul,
and John (not through verbal inspiration, but communication of thoughts).
The
interaction model I am proposing will be of most interest to one who is at
least willing to seriously consider the possibility that God has communicated
some propositional truths to Bible writers, who have communicated them in
language understandable to modern humankind.
My
own area of training and research is in evolutionary biology and paleontology,
and I will discuss the integration of faith and scholarship mainly in these
fields, but similar principles could be applied to many other disciplines. In spite of current thinking in much of the
scholarly world, I choose the more conservative approach to biblical
interpretation as the more realistic one.
This approach must be used with wisdom, prayer, and careful thought, or
it can lead to simplistic ideas like a common fundamentalist belief in verbal
inspiration of Scripture (which some SDA’s have also tried to apply to Ellen
White). I will not attempt in this paper
to defend my conservative view of biblical interpretation, but will only
discuss the application of that concept in integrating faith and scholarship,
which I find to work very well.
Challenges to be overcome: the
pitfalls
The
attempt to integrate faith and scholarship introduces a tension. Religious belief, for a conservative, is
based on authority, and there is a tension between authority and free
inquiry. Are we willing to let the data
lead where they will? The nervousness of
Christian thought leaders about the idea of seeking a relationship between
science and religion cannot be lightly brushed aside (Brand 2000). Any suggested method for interaction of
science and faith must be developed with great care, and must have an answer
for the following five concerns.
1. Religion may introduce biases into our
science. Can religion introduce
biases into our scholarly search for truth?
It seems likely that it could.
One solution is to decide that the Bible must be put aside when we think
about science. Then religious biases
will not trouble us, and we can be more objective. There is a problem with that solution, which
is illustrated by an episode in the history of geology.
When
the discipline of geology was taking form the geologists Hutton (1795) and Lyell
(1830-1833) each wrote books in which they developed a paradigm of geology that
rejected the catastrophism of their day (the belief that many rock formations
were formed very rapidly; for some early geologists this was based on the
Bible), and replaced it with the theory that all geologic processes occur very
slowly and gradually (gradualism).
Lyell’s influential book constricted geology to a completely
gradualistic paradigm until the mid 20th century. Historical analysis of Lyell’s work has now
concluded that the catastrophists in Lyell’s day were the more unbiased
scientists, and Lyell took a culturally derived theory and imposed it upon the
data (Gould, 1984).
Lyell’s
strictly gradualistic theory was bad for geology. It closed geologists’ minds, preventing them
from considering any hypotheses that involved catastrophic interpretations of
geological data (Gould 1965; Krynine 1956; Valentine 1966). The authors just cited still prefer to
explain geology in a millions of years scenario, but they are simply
recognizing the evidence that many sedimentary deposits were catastrophic in
nature. Lyell’s paradigm prevented
geologists from recognizing the evidence for these catastrophic processes until
Lyell’s serious bias was recognized and at least partially abandoned. The evidence for catastrophic processes was
there in the rocks before, but if the ruling paradigm says it isn’t so, it will
probably not be recognized.
This
episode reveals that bias is not a religious problem. It’s a problem that we all have to contend
with, no matter what philosophy we adopt.
The idea that religion introduces biases, but scholarship that leaves
religion aside is objective, is naive.
We may read our pet ideas into the Bible, between the lines, and
misunderstand how to relate Scripture to nature. However, those who do not take Scripture
seriously (or literally) have their own problems with other biases, and these
are no less significant than the biases that can result from religion. An effective model for integration of faith
and science must include a bias-control process.
One
factor that greatly affects a person’s objectivity is their willingness to
seek, and take seriously, input from others.
If two persons with differing views are involved in the same type of research,
they are each likely to notice things that the other may overlook. Consequently they will both probably be more
successful if they seek to learn from each other. I believe that responsible efforts at
integration of religion and science can contribute to this process, by the
method described below, to the mutual benefit of both science and
religion.
In
summary, religion can introduce biases into our science, but so can any other
philosophical approach. The answer is to
be aware of the problem and consciously and critically analyze our efforts at
being objective, and to communicate with others regarding our ideas. Awareness of different points of view on an
issue generally improves our ability to recognize our biases and to reach a
defensible conclusion.
The
reverse of this is also true - if we do not seek to integrate science
and faith it is unlikely that we will adequately understand the areas where
science and religion speak to the same issues and seem to be in conflict. If we do not put forth serious effort to
challenge conventional thinking and develop a positive synthesis of science and
faith, we are likely to accept conventional thinking without knowing whether or
not it is based on a solid foundation.
2. Science may disprove our Christian belief
system. There could be a fear that
science will finally disprove our Christian belief system if we try to
integrate faith and scholarship. Are we
confident enough to accept that possibility?
It is possible that some of our specific beliefs about origins that
involve details not given in Scripture may be wrong, and it is better for us to
learn that. Ideas that are truly
God-given biblical truths, on the other hand, will not be disproved. Nature and revelation will not ultimately
contradict each other, for both came from the same God. It is often more comfortable for us to keep
our beliefs close to our hearts and not let science look at them, but if we do
that we will miss opportunities for discoveries that can vindicate our trust in
the Creator and help others to learn to trust Him also, while possibly also
revealing that some of our ideas are wrong and not biblical.
Of
course many would say that the above scenario has already happened - scientific
data on such topics as the age of life on earth have already disproved the
Genesis story. However, as we use
science to study questions of origins and biological history, there is a danger
that we should be aware of. Science has
for so long used naturalistic thinking to explain all the data, that it takes
diligent, careful study to see past those deeply-entrenched interpretations and
find new ways to understand the data.
Also scientific research typically does not yield its secrets quickly or
easily. It often takes years of effort
to resolve a difficult scientific puzzle, and only the persistent researcher
will succeed. A researcher with a
settled confidence in Scripture will at times have to stubbornly trust the God
of the Bible until they finally are able to understand the data (and some of
our questions will probably not be answered on this earth). That is what other scientists do when they
face difficulties in finding a fit between the data and conventional scientific
theory. They typically have confidence
that the theory will ultimately solve its problems. That is why Lakatos’s research programs
include a core theory which is protected from disproof by the protective belt
of auxiliary hypotheses.
Previous
experience suggests that we will continue to find strong evidences of the Creator’s
hand in biological history and earth history, but we will also struggle with
solutions to some difficult puzzles.
Radiometric data, e.g., seems to point strongly to a very long time for
life on earth, but some other evidence, in addition to Scripture, gives me
reasons to question that age. I believe
there is reason for much continued study of this topic.
In
summary, it is my observation that those who warn against attempts to integrate
science and faith are often persons who do not believe that the Bible gives
facts, but only “spiritual truths”. On
the other hand, if we have confidence in the truth of Scripture we don’t need
to fear honest research, but we must avoid superficial efforts or they could lead
us in wrong directions.
3. We may hold religious positions that are
ultimately not biblical, and scientific disproof of these positions will
discredit our faith unnecessarily.
The problem here is our tendency to read into the Bible, between the
lines, our pet ideas, or ideas that have become culturally ingrained but are
actually not in the Bible. For example
in Darwin’s time there was widespread Christian belief that all species of
animals and plants were created just as they are now, with no change since the
creation. In reality this idea cannot be
supported from the Bible, but came from Greek philosophy, and the concept was
“read into” such general phrases as “after his kind.” Scientific research has produced abundant
evidence that at least some biological change does occur, refuting this
supposedly biblical concept and further weakening the faith of some persons.
Nevertheless,
if we hold beliefs that are not biblical, don’t we want to find that out? Scientific knowledge at any given time
includes many beliefs that will later turn out to be false. That doesn’t keep scientists from pursuing
research, and ideally they readily admit when they discover new data that
change some scientific belief (especially if it challenges some other
scientist’s beliefs, rather than their own!).
Religious scientists can pursue research with the same confidence and
openness to change in our humanly devised ideas about details that aren’t given
in Scripture.
Problems
are caused by some creationists who devise very speculative theories about
origins, that go way beyond what is given in the Bible, and proclaim these as
TRUTH. When scientists encounter these
careless and embarrassing theories it does make our faith look bad. The problem here is not the effort to
integrate science and faith, but the careless and uninformed way that it was
done. The solution is not fear of
research or fear of the effort to integrate science and faith, but careful,
well-informed study, and also an honest attitude in areas where we do not have
adequate answers to difficult data.
4. The danger of returning to god-of-the-gaps
thinking. Another concern is that we
may drop back into the old god-of-the-gaps reasoning of an earlier era. In British natural theology of pre-Darwinian
times it was thought that the direct action of God should only be invoked in
processes for which we cannot find a natural explanation (God can be found
where there are gaps in our understanding).
The problem with this approach is that as science found explanations for
more and more processes in nature, these gaps were filled and God was pushed
farther and farther away and finally dispensed with altogether (or so it
seemed). In reality this was a logical
fallacy, because to describe something does not explain it. Our increased scientific knowledge has
increased our understanding of how God’s marvelous inventions work, but has not
shown how those inventions were produced or at what level God’s sustaining hand
still operates. The problem with the
god-of-the-gaps approach was that as more scientific explanations were found,
it tended to undermine faith in God.
Thus the concern about falling again into the god-of-the-gaps fallacy is
valid, and deserves an answer.
It
is important not to fall back into that trap.
It is not necessary to do so if we carefully examine our logic in our
integration efforts. One difference
today from previous centuries is that in some areas of science we have learned
enough for our arguments to be the opposite of the god-of-the gaps. For example in molecular biology the more we
learn, the more difficult it is to explain origins without a Creator. Instead of God being needed only where there
are gaps in our knowledge, the more data we collect, the more evident it
becomes that we need God in our explanations.
In other words, some gaps are getting wider, not narrower.
In
summary, fear of the god-of-the-gaps fallacy should not frighten us away from
efforts to integrate science and religion into a meaningful synthesis. It is important that we be aware of the
nature of various logical fallacies, like the god-of-the-gaps, and avoid them
by careful self-evaluation of our logic and by paying attention to other
scholars’ criticisms of our ideas. Just
because a task requires navigating around pitfalls is not a good reason to refuse
to tackle the task. Ask any of the great
explorers about that.
5.
Religious explanations (“God did it”)
may discourage scientific investigation.
An additional concern about integrating science and faith is that the
conclusion “God did it” may eliminate any further need or incentive for
scientific research, and consequently is bad for science.
The way some persons approach this
subject does have that effect. However,
it does not need to be that way. A
biblical position does suggest that some current scientific research is not
worthwhile, but it can also suggest new approaches to research that can, and
already are, resulting in productive science.
The examples discussed below illustrate this concept, and show how an
active interaction between science and Scripture can challenge us to more
careful and diligent research in both science and in our religion.
These
new approaches result from asking questions that others are not asking;
including questions that challenge or ignore assumptions based on a paradigm
that denies biblical concepts. The
assumptions of a discipline may be necessary to provide a framework for
interpreting evidence, but if they are never challenged they may also have the
side effect of protecting some concepts from rigorous thought and
research. Many and perhaps all
disciplines can benefit from careful scholarly work that digs deeper and seeks
to identify significant questions that are not being asked.
Those
who accept a non-creationist history of life, with life on earth for ~4 billion
years have a tendency to argue that even if it is hard to explain the origin of
life forms, the long time spans allow seemingly impossible things to
happen. This can have the very same
effect as relying on “God did it” to solve all problems. I will argue that relying on time to work the
miracles is, for many persons, shielding the study of life origins from
rigorous thought. Dawkins (1986, 1996,
1998) is a good example of this problem.
In
summary, an effective method for integrating faith and science must
encourage research in science and also more careful Bible study, stimulating
growth of knowledge in both areas. That
may seem like a tall order, but keep reading.
The interaction model for integration
of religion and science
This
model begins with the assumption that science is an open-ended search for
truth, and is not willing to accept any rules that will restrict the
search. Science as a game, following an
arbitrary set of rules, does not interest me.
One such arbitrary rule, the philosophy of Naturalism rejects any
hypotheses that imply supernatural intervention in the universe at any time,
past or present. But the absence of
unique events (supernatural or otherwise) should not be assumed, but should be
a hypothesis to be tested. If we wish to
consider whether there were such interventions, and to examine evidence
relevant to that question, naturalism must be set aside so that the search can
proceed unhindered.
Nancey
Murphy (1990) claims to have demonstrated that theology can use the scientific
method. She starts from the position
that in this age of scientific reasoning theology must justify its knowledge
claims by showing that theology’s methodology is consistent with scientific reasoning. She chose Lakatos’s philosophy of science as
the most sophisticated one available, and applied it to her examination of “a theological school (the Roman Catholic
Modernist movement from roughly 1890 to 1910) in order to see whether Lakatos’s
theory of scientific rationality allows for a reconstruction of the rationality
inherent in its development” (Murphy 1990, p. 88). She showed that it is reasonable to interpret
the Modernist movement and the development of its belief system as a core theory
(“Genuine Catholicism is the true faith and reconcilable with modern thought”)
with a belt of protective auxiliary hypotheses.
She showed how the core belief remained intact while the auxiliary
hypotheses changed as various scholars developed the thinking of the Modernist
movement. From this study she concluded
that theology does meet the standard of scientific rationality as represented
in Lakatos’s philosophy of science.
It
seems to me, however, that she missed the point in this research. Although Lakatos provides a convincing
description of the scientific process, we don’t accept the value of science
because it follows Lakatos’s method. We
accept science because it works - it improves our understanding of how
the universe functions. In the same way,
showing that theologians follow a Lakatos-like method does not validate
theology as a method for seeking truth.
Theology is of value if it works in revealing convincing truths
about God and human destiny. Murphy’s
research is only an analysis of the philosophy and sociology of religion, not
of the application of theology to analyzing truth claims.
Murphy
recognizes that her application of Lakatos’s theory of research programs “is
not as helpful as it might be in illustrating how the main business of theology
is to be carried on in its light” (Murphy 1990, p. 175). Later she mentions how the theologian
Pannenberg uses his theology to offer reinterpretations of data in
anthropology. She says “the prediction
and corroboration of some fact previously unanticipated by the anthropologists
at this point would go a long way toward establishing the scientific
respectability of Pannenberg’s theology” (Murphy 1990, p. 178). This is the most relevant example of Murphy’s
thesis that theology can stand up to the standards of the scientific method,
because Pannenberg made a prediction that can be tested by science, and thus
can test truth claims. This case is an
example of my own suggestion of how religion can suggest hypotheses or make
predictions that can stimulate scientific research. Murphy’s approach differs most from mine in her claim that “In
philosophy of religion the important point of contention is still whether it is
possible to be a rational theologian.
Here the game is won by anyone who can show that theology is in the same
ball park with science . . .” (Murphy 1990, p. 208; emphasis in original). I answer that science is not the standard for
judging theological method. Theology is
of little value unless God has communicated truths to us, and if He did, then
theology goes far beyond science and reveals things that science could never
figure out on its own, while science helps us to see where we have read
something into Scripture that isn’t there.
Plantinga
(1997) urges Christians to use all the information available to us, including
what we know as Christians, in seeking an understanding of our scholarly
disciplines. Others have also suggested
that statements about the world can be derived from Scripture and can be tested
by the methods of science (Moreland 1989; Ratzsch 2000). My purpose here is to develop that
concept. The primary distinguishing
features of this model are 1) science and religion challenge each other is
areas where they are in conflict, motivating more careful thought and research in
both areas. Religious concepts are not
tested by science, and scientific concepts are not directly tested by religion,
because we may misunderstand the information from both sources. By keeping them temporarily separate in our
mind, and letting each persistently challenge the other we are forced to dig
deeper in both science and religion and not accept superficial
explanations. Other features of the
model are: 2) religion can be a source of ideas, hypotheses, or predictions
that can be a stimulus for scientific research, and 3) these ideas are pursued
and tested with scientific research. The
scientific process used will be the same as that used by others, and will
differ only in the questions that are asked, the evidence likely to catch the
researchers attention, and the range of explanations open for
consideration. This is partly
illustrated in Figure 2 (from Brand 1997).
There
are definite limits to what science can do in this integration process. Science cannot study supernatural processes,
such as creation, or Jesus’ miracles.
Science can only do research on events or processes that can be
observed, or that have occurred and left evidence behind. If some unique event (miraculous or
otherwise) has influenced such events, science can study any evidence that was
left behind, and historical records could be used to make predictions regarding
such events. It doesn’t matter where
those ideas and records came from (even from the Bible). The source of an idea or hypothesis does not
influence the scientific legitimacy of the idea. If it can be evaluated by the scientific
process, it is a valid scientific idea (Popper 1959, p. 31, 32; Moreland 1989,
p. 229; Cromer 1993, p. 148).
Figure
2. Illustration of a method for
integration of science and religion. The
methods of scientific research and of religious study are different, and the
integration occurs in the thinking process called the interface. This occurs especially, but not only, when
conflicts occur between science and religion, stimulating more careful research
in both areas. Either science or
religion can suggest ideas that can be utilized in scientific research.
It is necessary to know God as a personal
friend and learn to trust Him and His Word, before we are likely to use
Scripture to effectively assist us in our scholarly thinking. That step may seem too subjective to be part
of a philosophy of science, but both science and theology must deal with
subjective elements. The viability of
this method depends on whether we can make it work to suggest testable
predictions or hypotheses. Meanwhile if
we interact with other scholars with various views, that interaction provides
bias-control and can help us avoid simplistic attempts to relate Scripture to
the natural world.
This
approach is not just a theory, but some of us have been using it for years and
find that it works very well.
Incorporating the following steps is effective in achieving results
while controlling the biases that can result from any world view: 1) actively search for and utilize insights
from Scripture in developing hypotheses pertinent to our discipline, and pursue
research attempting to test these hypotheses;
2) be aware of the work and thinking of those who have a different world
view; 3) whenever feasible, submit our work for publication and peer review; 4) become friends with those in a different
world view, and perhaps even do collaborative work with them. This requires the confidence and independence
of thought to not accept whatever our collaborators think, while maintaining a
constructive dialogue that can reduce the likelihood of superficial
thinking. A number of examples of this
research approach could be described (e.g. see Brand 1997), but here we will
consider just two examples.
Examples
Walls of Jericho - When the walls of Jericho fell
down, as described in Scripture, the result would be a pile of rubble. If we can now identify the ruins of Jericho,
we can study that pile of rubble. Science
would probably not be able to determine whether the walls fell from an earthquake
or from a divine push. However, before
beginning the archeological study we could use biblical information to predict
that the walls fell down suddenly, rather than disintegrating gradually through
time, and then test this hypothesis or prediction with the methods of science.
Fossil whales of the Miocene/Pliocene
Pisco Formation of Peru - The Pisco Formation in Peru contains a large number of fossil whales,
buried in a deposit of diatoms and other sediments. Microscopic diatoms are organisms that float
near the surface of lakes and oceans.
Upon death their silica skeletons sink, and in modern oceans they form
accumulations of diatomite a few centimeters thick in a thousand years. It is assumed that ancient (fossil) diatomite
deposits formed at the same slow rate - a few centimeters per thousand years,
which is consistent with radiometric dates indicating a time frame of several
million years for the Pisco Formation.
My biblical world view predicts that geological deposits like this
formed in a much shorter time frame - a maximum of hundreds or thousands rather
than millions of years.
Geologists
have published on the overall geology of the Pisco Formation, and
paleontologists have studied the whales and where they fit into evolutionary
scenarios. Apparently no one has
previously asked how it can be that sediment which accumulated at the slow rate
of a few centimeters per thousand years can contain complete, well-preserved
whales, which would seem to require rapid burial for their preservation. Our world view with its predictions of short
time periods opened our eyes to see things that others have not noticed. When I saw the Pisco Formation the
incongruity of the well-preserved whales as opposed to the presumed slow rate
of diatom accumulation hit me right between the eyes. Our research there during several summers, by
a team of geologists and paleontologists, has indicated that the whale
carcasses were not in any type of special situation that could favor
preservation of animals over extended time periods before burial. Our evidence points to rapid burial, probably
within a few weeks or months, not thousands of years, for any given whale, and
suggests some processes that can help to explain how ancient diatomites may
have accumulated much more rapidly than is usually assumed.
In
this research we have presented several papers at the annual meetings of the
Geological Society of America (attended by 5,000+ geologists and
paleontologists) and at an international paleontological conference in Spain. These presentations provided opportunity for
interacting with other scientists who deal with these topics. We have published two papers
(Esperante-Caamano et al. 2002; Brand et al. 2004) and have several more
manuscripts in preparation. The best
scientists in the field have opportunity to evaluate our work, and will be
eager to point out any mistakes. That
is a powerful incentive to keep us from being careless. Of course we will not discuss biblical
insights at the geology meetings or in our publications, as that would not be
appropriate. We will discuss scientific
work only, and if the data support our conclusions our work will stand up to
the criticisms of scientific reviewers.
In
the research described above our research method was not different from the
method used by other scientists. The
data potentially available to us, the data we used, the laboratory methods for
analyzing samples (XRD, XRF, scanning electron microscopy, examination of thin
sections, etc.) were the same as for anyone else. The only differences were in the questions we
asked, the types of evidence most likely to catch our attention (primarily
affected by the questions we asked), the range of possible interpretations
considered (These will include a much shorter time frame than many scientists
would prefer), and the predictions made by our worldview.
Our
predictions and hypotheses must be tested in the same way as anyone else will
test scientific predictions and hypotheses, and these tests will have to stand
up to the normal scientific peer-review process. Although other earth scientists did not
recognize the need to reevaluate the rate of accumulation of diatoms in the
Pisco Formation, the reviewers of our manuscripts, in the fields of taphonomy
and diatom studies, agreed that the data supported our conclusions.
It
must be emphasized that this model does not introduce a different scientific
process of data collection or analysis or data interpretation. The novel feature is simply taking Scripture
as a source of valid information, and using that information to suggest new
hypotheses to be tested, and new questions to be asked, that we
probably would not have thought of otherwise.
It opens our eyes to see things that we might otherwise have
overlooked. At that point it is then up
to us to use science to rigorously test these novel ideas, and see if they will
stand up to the best scientific procedures and bias control of peer
review.
In
the above examples information from Scripture influenced hypothesis-formation
in science. The process also goes the
other way. Experience in geology
research has led some of us to recognize that a common assumption among
conservative Christians is actually not biblical - the assumption that all or
most of the fossil record formed during the global flood of Genesis. It is not unbiblical to suggest that part of
the record formed before and part after the flood.
Theological implications of the
interaction model
This
philosophy for integrating science and religion yields a consistent, rational
explanation for the origin of life and of pain and suffering. A conservative reading of Scripture portrays
a cosmic conflict between God and a created being, called Satan. God created the universe and life to function
harmoniously, and humans were initially innocent and sinless. But humans and other intelligent cosmic
beings were not made as obedient computers; their brains were designed by God
with the ability to make free choices.
Satan and humans made the wrong choice, and sin, pain, and suffering for
the human race resulted from this choice.
The suffering thus initiated has affected not only humans, but their sin
was also a choice to permit Satan to exert his influence on the earth and on
all life on the earth. The ultimate
result has been pain, death, disease, and changes in the geological structure
of the earth, producing natural disasters such as floods, earthquakes, and
storms. These were not punishments for
sin, but were the natural result of sin and the allowing of Satan to exert his influence
on the earth and its inhabitants.
Jesus’s death and resurrection in some way earned Him the right to
redeem humans from their sin, and give the gift of eternal life, on a recreated
planet, to those who accept the gift.
This gift will be received when the cosmic conflict is ended and it has
become evident that God’s way is best after all. This is important because God honors our
freedom of choice, including our freedom to choose to accept the consequences of
our choice. In eternity He will not force
us to obey, but the history of the cosmic conflict will convince those who have
accepted eternal life that it would be foolish to rebel again. These theological concepts cannot be studied
by science, but they are the logical result of a particular philosophy of the
relationship between religion and science.
For me personally, the coherent explanation of pain and suffering
resulting from my application of Model 3, in contrast with the explanation
offered in Model 2, is a powerful argument in favor of the epistemological
approach underlying Model 3.
Of
course this philosophy requires that humans actually were created in a creation
event that predated the formation of the sequence of fossils in the fossil
record. If pain, suffering, death, and
geological hazards like earthquakes and volcanoes resulted from human sin, then
humans could not have evolved from ape-like ancestors near the end of
geological history, but had to have been in existence from the beginning of
life’s history on earth.
This
challenges some of science’s contemporary interpretations, and predicts that a
number of significant phenomena are yet to be discovered, especially in the
areas of geology, paleontology, and radiometric dating. For example, as far as science understands,
the earth’s crust and the mantle that it rides on are very viscous, and only
move extremely slowly - currently about 1-4 cm per year (Burchfiel 2004). This concept is often cited as evidence that
a biblical time frame from creation to the present is impossible, because the
rapid continental movements required by that time frame are impossible. But we are told that at the time of Jesus’s
return “The whole earth heaves and swells like the waves of the sea. Its surface is breaking up. . . Mountain chains are sinking. Inhabited islands disappear” (GC 636). Such crustal fluidity and rapid movement is
very unrealistic if current geophysical interpretations are true. Yet God has told us that when He involves
Himself in physical processes on earth, things may function quite differently
from what we have observed in our lifetimes.
Also,
when Jesus told a man with a withered hand to stretch it out, and it was
healed, and when Jesus, at his arrest, healed the soldier’s severed ear, God
had to create healthy tissue at that moment.
Majority scientific opinion would have us believe such a thing to be
impossible. But if God has communicated
trustworthy statements to us (and what other conclusion could be consistent
with the way Jesus intimately related to us by His life?), then these
statements about the crust of the earth and Jesus’s instant creations support
the interaction model for integrating religion and science. They do so by giving us insights into how far
some physical and biological processes can vary from modern observed processes,
when God brings His influence to bear on them.
Many
scientists object strongly to such proposed divine interventions that don’t
follow the normal course of natural processes.
However, if these interventions did occur (and Scripture says or implies
they did), is it better for science to recognize them, or to pretend they
didn’t happen? Perhaps the reason
Scripture tells us about the creation and flood and gives us insights into the
amount of time represented is because God knew we would have trouble correctly
interpreting the complex evidence from the ancient past without these
insights.
If
we don’t seek to learn from God’s communications to us and even use them to
inform our science, then science, not God, has priority in our thinking, and
our science will lead us in incorrect directions. Our understanding of philosophy of science
has direct relevance to this issue.
Modern understanding of the philosophy of science reminds us that we
cannot verify theories - science does not know for sure what are the limits of
truth about the universe. It is not
realistic for science to insist that its understanding of geophysics, e.g., is
correct and complete, and that there are no new physical principles yet to be
discovered - even principles as radical as rapidly moving continental
crust. Science cannot at this time
support such a hypothesis of rapid continental movements, but it also cannot
legitimately deny the possibility that there might be undiscovered physical
principles that would allow that hypothesis to be true.
Conclusions
It
seems that Christianity with its rational, consistent God provided the context
for modern science to develop. However,
beginning with the Enlightenment science tried to define itself in a way that denies theology any legitimate
right to influence science or even to claim to have knowledge. Twentieth century philosophers of science
found the older philosophies of science increasingly unworkable, as they
realized how human, science and scientists are.
With this new realization that a clear line cannot be drawn between
science and non-science, it has become unrealistic to deny theology as a
possible source of knowledge. This opens
the door to suggest that the integration of religion and science is a worthwhile
goal. Religion can suggest hypotheses
for science to think about, as well as
the reverse.
In
spite of these developments, many scientists interpret nature within the
framework of naturalism - no hypotheses are allowed that would imply any divine
intervention any time in history. This
philosophy does not allow any attempt to integrate religion and science. A second model for the relation between
religion and science (parallel but separate) accepts both religion and science
as sources of truth, but religion is still not allowed to influence
science. As a result, living things,
including humans, are believed to be the result of evolution. There was no Adam and Eve and no fall into
sin. Thus the Christian doctrine of
salvation also is rejected. Pain,
suffering, and death are interpreted as the necessary result of the generation
of life through evolution, and even god couldn’t prevent that.
The
third model (interaction) accepts both science and religion (Scripture) as
sources of knowledge, and recommends an active effort to integrate them. When they conflict, this stimulates more
careful study of both, seeking to understand them better and search for an
interpretation that is in harmony with both.
Since God has given us Scripture, it contains insights that go beyond
what science can offer; insights that we would not likely discover with science
alone. This model supports an
interpretation of the origin of pain, suffering and death that is rational and consistent,
in contrast with the other models.
There
is an important relationship between religion and the philosophy of science,
since an incorrect philosophy will lead us away from biblical truth, if we are
logically consistent. A correct
philosophy of science facilitates a constructive integration of religion and
science, making use of all that we as Christians know from Scripture. We can even utilize that knowledge to open
our eyes to potential new discoveries in science. Christians have an exciting opportunity to
follow God’s leading in this integration process, to demonstrate to a skeptical
modern world that Christianity speaks not just to the emotions, but also
reaches the mind and challenges it to reach beyond a mere human view of the
universe, and to grasp a truly harmonious understanding of its origin and
destiny.
References
Barbour, I. G. 1974. Myth,
Models and Paradigms. New York:
Harper & Row, Publishers.
_____. 1990. Religion
in an Age of Science. San
Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.
Behe, M. 1996. Darwin’s
Black Box. New York: Free Press.
Brand, L. 1997. Faith,
Reason, and Earth History: A Paradigm of Earth and Biological Origins by
Intelligent Design. Berrien Springs,
MI: Andrews University Press.
_____. 2000.
The Bible and Science. P. 139-162
In: Rasi, H. M. (ed.), Symposium on the Bible and Adventist Scholarship. Christ in the Classroom, Vol. 26-B. Silver Spring, MD: Institute for Christian Teaching. Dept. of Education, General Conference of
SDA’s.
_____, R. Esperante, A. Chadwick, O.
Poma, and M. Alomia. 2004. Fossil whale preservation implies high diatom
accumulation rate in the Miocene-Pliocene Pisco Formation of Peru. Geology, 32:65-68.
Burchfiel, B. C. 2004.
New technology; new geological challenges. GSA Today, 14 (2):4-9.
Cromer, A. 1993. Uncommon Sense: The Heretical Nature
of Science. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Dawkins, R. 1986. The Blind Watchmaker. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
____.
1996. Climbing Mount
Improbable. NY: W. W. Norton and Co.
____.
1998. Unweaving the Rainbow:
Science, Delusion and the Appetite for Wonder. New York: Houghton Mifflin Co.
Dembski, W. A. (ed.) 1998. Mere
Creation: Science, Faith & Intelligent Design. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
____.
1999. Intelligent Design.
Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
____ and J. M. Kushiner. 2001. Signs
of Intelligence: Understanding Intelligent Design. Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press.
Eldredge, N. 1982. The
Monkey Business: A Scientist Looks at Creationism. New York: Pocket Books (Washington Square
Press).
_____. 2001. The
Triumph of Evolution and the Failure of Creationism. New York: Henry Holt and Company.
Esperante-Caamano, R., L. Brand, A.
Chadwick, and O. Poma. 2002. Taphonomy of fossil whales in the
diatomaceous sediments of the Miocene/Pliocene Pisco Formation, Peru. pp. 337-343 In: De Renzi, M., M.
Alonso, M. Belinchon, E. Penalver, P. Montoya, and A. Marquez-Aliaga
(eds.). Current Topics on Taphonomy
and Fossilization. International
Conference Taphos 2002. 3rd
Meeting on Taphonomy and Fossilization, Valencia, Spain.
Feyerabend, P. 1978. Against
Method. New York: Verso.
_____. 1987. Farewell
to Reason. New York: Verso.
Futuyma, D. J. 1995. Science
on Trial: The Case for Evolution.
Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates, Inc.
Gould, S. J. 1965.
Is uniformitarianism necessary? American Journal of Science 263:223-228.
_____ ____.
1984. Lyell's vision and rhetoric. In: Berggren, W. A., and J. A. Van Couvering,
eds. Catastrophes and Earth
History: The New Uniformitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hutton, J. 1795. Theory of the Earth With Proofs and
Illustrations. 2 vols. William Creech, Edinburgh. (Reprinted 1959. H. R. Engelmann (J. Cramer) and Wheldon and
Wesley, LtD., Weinheim)
Johnson, P. E. 1991. Darwin
on Trial. Downers Grove, IL:
InterVarsity Press.
____.
1995. Reason in the Balance:
The Case Against Naturalism in Science, Law & Education. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
____.
1997. Defeating Darwinism by
Opening Minds. Downers Grove, IL:
InterVarsity Press.
____.
2000. The Wedge of Truth:
Splitting the Foundations of Naturalism.
Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Kitcher, P. 1982. Abusing
Science: The Case Against Creationism.
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Kuhn, T. 1962. The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
_____. 1970. The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
2nd ed. Chicago, IL:
The University of Chicago Press.
_____ (eds. J. Conant and J.
Haugeland). 2000. The Road Since Structure. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago
Press.
Krynine, P. D. 1956.
Uniformitarianism is a dangerous doctrine. Journal of Paleontology 30:1003-1004.
Lakatos, I. 1978. The
Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Philosophical Papers Volume 1. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Laudan, L. 1977. Progress
and its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Lyell, C. 1830-1833.
Principles of Geology, Being an Attempt to Explain the Former Changes
of the Earth’s Surface, by Reference to Causes Now in Operation. 3 vols.
John Murray, London. (1892. Principles of Geology, or the Modern
Changes of the Earth and its Inhabitants Considered as Illustrative of Geology. 11th ed.
2 vols. D. Appleton and Co., New
York) (the 11th edition is the most commonly used edition today)
Moreland, J. P. 1989. Christianity
and the Nature of Science. Grand
Rapids, MI: Baker Book House.
____ (ed.). 1994. The
Creation Hypothesis: Scientific Evidence for an Intelligent Designer. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Murphy, N. 1990. Theology
in the Age of Scientific Reasoning.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
_____. 1997. Reconciling
Theology and Science. Kitchener,
Ontario: Pandora Press.
_____. 2002. Religion
and Science: God, Evolution, and the Soul.
Kitchener, Ontario: Pandora Press.
National Academy of Sciences. 1999. Science
and Creationism: A View from the National Academy of Sciences. 2nd ed. Washington, D. C.: National Academy Press.
Peacocke, A. 1993. Theology
for a Scientific Age. Minneapolis,
MN: Fortress Press.
Plantinga, A. 1997.
On Christian scholarship.
Http://id-www/ucsb.edu/fscf/library/plantinga/OCS.html.
Polkinghorne, J. 1994. Quarks,
Chaos and Christianity. New York:
Crossroad.
_____. 1998. Science
and Theology: An Introduction.
Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.
_____. 2000. Faith,
Science and Understanding. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Pennock, R. T. 1999.
Tower of Babel: The Evidence Against the New Creationism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Popper, K. R. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper & Row.
_____. 1963.
Science: problems, aims, responsibilities. Federation Proceedings, 22:961-972.
Ratzsch, D. 2000. Science
and its Limits: The Natural Sciences in Christian Perspective. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
_____. 2001. Nature,
Design and Science: the Status of Design in Natural Science. Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press.
Reichenbach, H. 1951. The
Rise of Scientific Philosophy.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Ruse, M. (Ed.) 1996. But
is it Science: The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution
Controversy. Amherst, New York:
Prometheus Books.
Spetner, L. 1998. Not
by Chance. Brooklyn, NY: The Judaica
Press.
Valentine, J. W. 1966.
The present is the key to the present. Journal of Geological Education 14(2):59-60.
3/25/2004